Difference between revisions of "Team:SDU-Denmark/Tour22"
Line 30: | Line 30: | ||
<span class="tooltip"> | <span class="tooltip"> | ||
<span class="tooltipHeader">Reference:</span> | <span class="tooltipHeader">Reference:</span> | ||
− | Rene Descartes, | + | Rene Descartes, Meditationer over den første filosofi. Publisher: Det Lille Forlag 1. edition, published 19.04.2002. |
</span> | </span> | ||
Line 36: | Line 36: | ||
<span class="tooltip"> | <span class="tooltip"> | ||
<span class="tooltipHeader">Reference:</span> | <span class="tooltipHeader">Reference:</span> | ||
− | + | Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (General Historical Collections). Publisher: British Library, Historical Print Editions. Published 25.03.2011 | |
+ | <br> | ||
+ | ISBN-13: 9781241475611 | ||
</span> | </span> | ||
Jeremy Bentham was utilitarian and meant that the most important criterion for having rights should be the ability to feel pain, and therefor the wellbeing of animals should also be considered. | Jeremy Bentham was utilitarian and meant that the most important criterion for having rights should be the ability to feel pain, and therefor the wellbeing of animals should also be considered. |
Revision as of 09:52, 17 September 2015
"The question is not, "Can they reason?" nor, "Can they talk?" but "Can they suffer?”" ― Jeremy Bentham, The Principles of Morals and Legislation
Animal Ethics
Experimenting on animals goes as far back as to the 4th and 3rd centuries BCE and
the attitude towards animal rights has shifted a quite many times.
The issue then, is the same as today.
Can experimenting on animals reach a universal ethical justification or do we have to rely on particularism?
What kind of rights should animal have?
Choosing the universalistic approach means that we will have to provide some arguments that cannot be refuted, and make sure that these arguments could be applied to all situations at all times and at any place.
The particularistic approach gives every single situation its “own” ethical code. That means that what is right in situation A, can be wrong in situation B.
This seems at first sight as the most natural intuition, but digging just a bit deeper shows that its consequences is to radical and the boundaries between right and wrong becomes blurred.
Through history many philosophers have joined the debate about animal rights.
The first philosophical rationalist, Renè Descartes (1596-1650), was certain that animals were mere machines without souls and therefor had no rights at all.
They cannot feel pain and when they scream it is to be compared with the sound it makes when one breaks a stick or throws a stone into the water.
Reference:
Rene Descartes, Meditationer over den første filosofi. Publisher: Det Lille Forlag 1. edition, published 19.04.2002.
A hundred years later one of the first proponents of animal rights came along, Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832).
Reference:
Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (General Historical Collections). Publisher: British Library, Historical Print Editions. Published 25.03.2011
ISBN-13: 9781241475611
Jeremy Bentham was utilitarian and meant that the most important criterion for having rights should be the ability to feel pain, and therefor the wellbeing of animals should also be considered.
From the utilitarian point of view, an action is ethical correct if the outcome produces the highest possible amount of happiness overall.
How to measure happiness is still a huge challenge for utilitarians.
Now that I have sketched up two opposite philosophical positions concerning animal rights I will turn my attention to the present ethical approach. Today the general argument for justifying experimenting on animals is that opposite humans, non-human beings do not have the experience of the past and they do not expect their future. But that is problematic. Because if that is the criterions then why should we not experiment on brain-dead humans or infants? An argument can also be the fact that because we are able to control these animals they are of lesser worth than humans and therefor they can serve as tools for us. But this straightforward argument is also extremely conflicting with our view on our selves as caring reasonable beings. There is no bulletproof argument for why it is okay to decide that some animals are born in a laboratory, endures experiments its whole lifespan and at the end gets killed. The debate on experimenting on animals is not in any way an easy ethical discussion, but fortunately there has from scientific integrity sprung an initiative to find a middle ground. It is called the 3Rs; refinement, reduction and replacement. The Three Rs are ethical guidelines for use of animals in testing. These were first described by, W.M.S. Russell and R.L. Burch in 1959.
-
Refinement refers to methods that minimizes pain, or distress, and enhance animal welfare for the animals used.
-
Reduction refers to methods that enable scientists to obtain comparable levels of information from fewer animals, or to obtain more information from the same number of animals.
-
Replacement refers to the preferred use of non-animal methods over animal methods whenever it is possible to achieve the same scientific aims. Reference: (Link)
Even though the 3Rs is widely accepted and the use of dogs, pigs, primates, cats etc. are decreasing, the overall use of animals in experiments are increasing. This is caused by an escalating use of mice and GM-animals. Experiments are being done to 100 million vertebrates annually according to British Union for the Abolition of Vivisection Reference: Cruelty Free International, (Link) , and it does not count invertebrates like shrimps and flies, nor does it count animals bred for research and then killed as surplus.
We can only hope that the success of our P.A.S.T. project really can support the process towards lesser animals in laboratories.